Max Weber (1864-1920) perhaps more than any other figure of this time represents the–ultimately–failed attempt to bring about a democratic order in Weimar Germany. Despite these failings in political life, Weber is still generally considered to be the most important sociological thinker ever. http://www.isa-sociology.org/books/vt/bkv_000.htm. Weber helped found the German Democratic Party (DDP) which along with the Social Democratic Party and the Catholic Center Party tried to establish the left-liberal leaning Weimar Coalition in 1919. However this coalition failed to maintain power after 1920, from that point on any majority in parliament would have to include at least one of the more right-wing nationalistic and anti-democratic parties. The weakest link in the coalition was the DDP, although all parties lost support, which failed to attract voters as did many other newly created parties, instead voters withdrew from politics or joined private associations many of which had an authoritarian element to them.
“Politics as a Vocation” (Politik als Beruf) was a speech delivered by Weber to the students at the University of
Munich in the Southern German state of Bavaria during the revolution in December 1918, published the following month, the same month as the failed Spartacus uprising. Apart from the revolution in Berlin, the capital of the German Empire,
where Rosa Luxemburg was based, revolutionary movements spread out throughout
all the major cities of Germany, one of which was Munich the capital of the
state of Bavaria.
Before the Kaiser had formally vacated power,
revolutionaries had overthrown the 700-year old Wittelsbach dynasty that ruled Bavaria on November 7th
1918. Germany had such a dense feudal structure that they had overlapping
layers of monarchies, along with nobles, and all of the bishops and other officials who attended
to the kings and nobles. I had mentioned previously that Germany had a federal
system like the United States. That means that there was a division of power
between the national government and smaller states that make up the nation.
Unlike the U.S. which was a federal system made up of smaller republics, the
German state was made up of smaller monarchies (and a few “free cities”) that
were unified together in 1871. Perhaps since Germany became a unified state in 1871 it could help explain why states like Bavaria would separate itself from the rest of Germany. However this begs the question why did Germany become a unified state so late, especially in comparison to other states like England, France, Spain, and Russia?
Before there was a German Empire (or Second Reich) there was the Holy Roman Empire (First Reich). The French philosopher Voltaire once said, the Holy Roman Empire is neither Holy, nor Roman, nor an Empire, it definitely was not Roman, although it claimed to be the successor to the Roman Empire, and it was not really an Empire either, nonetheless, it remained in existence for almost 900 years from the coronation of Otto the Great in 962 until it was dissolved during the Napoleonic wars in 1806.
Following an ancient German tribal practice of electing kings, the emperor was elected by several of the most influential German princes. As this practice became institutionalized it gave the nobles much more power over the monarch, and thus prevented the consolidation of the state under one monarch, the opposite of what happened in England, France, and Spain. Besides the power of the nobility, there were also powerful independent city-states that were able to preserve some autonomy from either the monarch or the nobility. Germany today is made up of 16 states, however, three of those states are still "city-states," Berlin, Hamburg, and Bremen.
In addition to power of the "electors" to choose the emperor there was an Imperial Legislature or Diet, that also checked the power of the emperor. The Imperial Diet was composed of three levels: at the highest level were the electors, the second level was made up of the other princes, and the third level, representatives from the city-states. In other words the very political institutions of the empire itself seemed to work against its consolidation into a unified state under an absolute monarch. However it did allow for a common German culture to develop in its territories, that created a sense of "German identity" that existed for centuries before there was a German state, some have argued that this can even partly explain why Germany has such a developed culture and a relatively underdeveloped tradition of democracy. In the Eastern areas where there was less industry the nobles had even more power and even more independent from the monarch. Bavaria was one of the eastern states, Prussia was another. After Napoleon dissolved the Holy Roman Empire, he organized some of the German states including Bavaria into the Confederation of the Rhine (Rheinbund), after the Rhine River which runs through Germany–Prussia remained nominally independent but had to cede territory to this new Confederation.
The philosopher Hegel, who was completing the Phenomenology of Spirit at the same Napoleon was invading Prussia in 1806, regarded Napoleon as the world spirit, speaking to the sense of "cultural lag" that many Germanys saw in the old form of the empire. After the fall of Napoleon the boundaries of Europe were redrawn at the Congress of Vienna in 1815. As a result of this conference the German Confederation (Deutscher Bund) with the addition of Austria.
This confederation lasted until 1866 when still independent Prussia went to war against Austria leading to the North German Confederation (Norddeutscher Bund) which lasted until German unification in 1871.
In the 18th century Prussia began to become dominant over the other German states. Berlin, unlike some of the other German cities that went back to the time of the Romans, was founded in the 12th century. Over time the local Prussian elector-ruler allied itself with the Prussian nobles to reassert power over the growing independence of the peasant, farmer class, and with little resistance from the towns, the landowners became dominant and became institutionalized within the Prussian state. Scholars argued that it was this top-down modernization initiated by the landowning class with a subordinate bourgeoisie led the Prussian state into becoming a fascist state. Again this argument only reinforces the point that liberalism, as seen through its "carrier" the bourgeoisie was marginalized and relatively powerless throughout German history.
Munich is the capital of Bavaria which is the largest state by territory and the second largest in population in Germany. It has a larger population than both the Czech Republic and Austria which border it. The Bavarian state enjoys a higher degree of autonomy than most of the other German states, even being allowed to maintain its own army, and even today the ruling Christian Democratic Party (CDU) has a separate Bavarian party the Christian Social Union of Bavaria (CSU), in parliament the parties are grouped together as CDU/CSU. BMW is headquartered in Bavaria which stands for Bayerische Motern Werke or "Bavarian Motor Works," among the many other corporations also there.
Before there was a German Empire (or Second Reich) there was the Holy Roman Empire (First Reich). The French philosopher Voltaire once said, the Holy Roman Empire is neither Holy, nor Roman, nor an Empire, it definitely was not Roman, although it claimed to be the successor to the Roman Empire, and it was not really an Empire either, nonetheless, it remained in existence for almost 900 years from the coronation of Otto the Great in 962 until it was dissolved during the Napoleonic wars in 1806.
At its peak the territories covered by the Empire besides Germany: Austria, Czech Republic, Slovenia, Switzerland, Luxembourg, Belgium, the Netherlands, Poland and even parts of France and Italy |
Following an ancient German tribal practice of electing kings, the emperor was elected by several of the most influential German princes. As this practice became institutionalized it gave the nobles much more power over the monarch, and thus prevented the consolidation of the state under one monarch, the opposite of what happened in England, France, and Spain. Besides the power of the nobility, there were also powerful independent city-states that were able to preserve some autonomy from either the monarch or the nobility. Germany today is made up of 16 states, however, three of those states are still "city-states," Berlin, Hamburg, and Bremen.
In addition to power of the "electors" to choose the emperor there was an Imperial Legislature or Diet, that also checked the power of the emperor. The Imperial Diet was composed of three levels: at the highest level were the electors, the second level was made up of the other princes, and the third level, representatives from the city-states. In other words the very political institutions of the empire itself seemed to work against its consolidation into a unified state under an absolute monarch. However it did allow for a common German culture to develop in its territories, that created a sense of "German identity" that existed for centuries before there was a German state, some have argued that this can even partly explain why Germany has such a developed culture and a relatively underdeveloped tradition of democracy. In the Eastern areas where there was less industry the nobles had even more power and even more independent from the monarch. Bavaria was one of the eastern states, Prussia was another. After Napoleon dissolved the Holy Roman Empire, he organized some of the German states including Bavaria into the Confederation of the Rhine (Rheinbund), after the Rhine River which runs through Germany–Prussia remained nominally independent but had to cede territory to this new Confederation.
Flag of Confederation of Rhine 1806-1813 |
The philosopher Hegel, who was completing the Phenomenology of Spirit at the same Napoleon was invading Prussia in 1806, regarded Napoleon as the world spirit, speaking to the sense of "cultural lag" that many Germanys saw in the old form of the empire. After the fall of Napoleon the boundaries of Europe were redrawn at the Congress of Vienna in 1815. As a result of this conference the German Confederation (Deutscher Bund) with the addition of Austria.
German Confederation 1815-1866 |
This confederation lasted until 1866 when still independent Prussia went to war against Austria leading to the North German Confederation (Norddeutscher Bund) which lasted until German unification in 1871.
North German Confederation 1867-1871 |
In the 18th century Prussia began to become dominant over the other German states. Berlin, unlike some of the other German cities that went back to the time of the Romans, was founded in the 12th century. Over time the local Prussian elector-ruler allied itself with the Prussian nobles to reassert power over the growing independence of the peasant, farmer class, and with little resistance from the towns, the landowners became dominant and became institutionalized within the Prussian state. Scholars argued that it was this top-down modernization initiated by the landowning class with a subordinate bourgeoisie led the Prussian state into becoming a fascist state. Again this argument only reinforces the point that liberalism, as seen through its "carrier" the bourgeoisie was marginalized and relatively powerless throughout German history.
Munich is the capital of Bavaria which is the largest state by territory and the second largest in population in Germany. It has a larger population than both the Czech Republic and Austria which border it. The Bavarian state enjoys a higher degree of autonomy than most of the other German states, even being allowed to maintain its own army, and even today the ruling Christian Democratic Party (CDU) has a separate Bavarian party the Christian Social Union of Bavaria (CSU), in parliament the parties are grouped together as CDU/CSU. BMW is headquartered in Bavaria which stands for Bayerische Motern Werke or "Bavarian Motor Works," among the many other corporations also there.
Bavarian Socialist Republic 1918-1919 Bavarian Soviet Republic 1919 |
It may seem surprising that a state would declare itself autonomous from the larger state it is part of, however it is important to remember, that for over 40 years after World War II, Germany was divided into two separate nations, West Germany and East Germany, only this time the Northeastern part of Germany becomes the communist East German state and Bavaria remains in the capitalist West German state while. Most of the major industrial cities in Germany are in the West: Hamburg, Bonn (the capital of West Germany), Cologne, Bremen, Frankfurt am Main, where the Frankfurt School is and the financial capital of Germany; further South is Stuttgart where the automobile was invented, and Munich, the capital of Bavaria which was also where the tragic killing of the Israeli Olympic team took place in 1972.
The capital, Berlin, is in the East, however, and the stories of the standoff between American and Soviet forces in Berlin are well known, most famously the Berlin Wall built in 1961. In contemporary German politics there is intense debate over government spending over the more impoverished, less developed East. Many people in the West resent having to pay taxes to provide government services and welfare to the East. The former East German communist party, The Socialist Unity Party of Germany, also continues to exist, first renamed Party of Democratic Socialism, now just "The Left" (Die Linke) and is the fourth largest out of the five party groups represented in the German parliament, the Bundestag (Federal Diet).
Weber was addressing a revolutionary audience. Kurt Eisner, leader of the Bavaria USPD party, seized power
in November 1918 and proclaimed the Bavarian Socialist Republic. The USPD
became the centrist party in the post-revolutionary political structure; both
the SPD and the Spartacus group competed for their alliance. In this case the
USPD under Eisner was more to the left (closer to the Spartacus group), the
socialist republic proclaimed its independence from the rest of Germany. In
February 1919 a right-wing extremist assassinated Eisner. In April the state is
renamed the Bavarian Soviet Republic and becomes a satellite of the Soviet
Union. In May the Bavarian Soviet Republic is crushed by force after the
Bavarian army and Freikorps (squads of
decommissioned soldiers returning from the front lines) invade Munich killing
almost 2,000 and injuring thousands more. By August the Weimar Constitution
takes effect and Bavaria is reintegrated into the Weimar Republic.
The capital, Berlin, is in the East, however, and the stories of the standoff between American and Soviet forces in Berlin are well known, most famously the Berlin Wall built in 1961. In contemporary German politics there is intense debate over government spending over the more impoverished, less developed East. Many people in the West resent having to pay taxes to provide government services and welfare to the East. The former East German communist party, The Socialist Unity Party of Germany, also continues to exist, first renamed Party of Democratic Socialism, now just "The Left" (Die Linke) and is the fourth largest out of the five party groups represented in the German parliament, the Bundestag (Federal Diet).
Note that Germany is almost completely surrounded by other states. |
Weber himself was a liberal and not a socialist, and was mostly critical of the social democratic parties throughout his life. He was a well-connected individual who had access to the highest officials in power, and he commanded significant authority for his singular scholarly achievements–a true insider. He was also a defender of German nationalism and imperialism. He also defended the controversial Article 48 in the Constitution that later gave Adolf Hitler the legal pretext to seize dictatorial power. The context of the speech suggests it is an instructional manual on politics delivered to a revolutionary student’s organization while the revolution is going on. This would be similar if a well-connected political insider came down to Occupy Wall Street and taught them about politics and organization, this never happened though. Weber himself did not live much longer than the soviet republic and died a year later in 1920, at 56, a victim of the “Spanish flu” the 1918 influenza pandemic triggered by World War I.
The failure of the revolution sets the stage for a counter-revolution. Munich becomes one of the earliest breeding grounds of
Nazism. Hitler staged an attempt at seizing power in Munich with former Supreme
Commander Erich Luddendorf in 1923. He failed and was put in jail for four
years. Ten years later, Hitler would legally be appointed Chancellor of Germany
(Reichskanzler), before renaming himself
the Fürher in 1934.
The “state” (staat), is the dominant political organization and the object of the study of politics. Weber famously defines the ideal type of the state: as the organization that maintains a monopoly on the use of force (macht) over a given territory. All political orders are maintained through the use of force. This is a sobering lesson for people undergoing a revolution and something which those who have been leading the movement are already discovering, both from themselves and from their opponents. Power is wielded over a certain territorial area, the geography of the territory partially determines the character of the state. Otherwise the concentration of power over a certain area gives rise to distinctive nationalities who identify with the state and its particular form of domination. Weber is careful to define the state only in terms of means, not ends. The means the state uses, is force, the end, the goals it pursues is relative to the unique history of each state. The ends of the state today are termed the “national interests” of the state.
"The Calling of St. Matthew," Caravaggio, 1599-1600, Rome |
Weber draws upon this meaning while redefining it in a secular way, to refer to devotion to one’s work and through that finding a sense of fulfillment and purpose in life. “Vocational training” also refers to the teaching of “procedural knowledge” and is used to refer to the teaching of trades like carpentry or plumbing that require specific technical knowledge. He develops this concept for professional politicians to what he refers to as status honor a sense of achievement deriving from the ability to perform the work processes that are necessary to carry out political decisions.
At the same time everyone who lives ‘for’ politics (vocation), also lives ‘off’ politics (avocation) in that they are financially dependent upon politics for a livelihood. However, the typical way in which politics, status honor, and meaning intersect and mediate each other is through nationalism. The nation then becomes the substitute for the loss of meaning in traditional authorities caused by the rise of nihilistic thought in the late 19th century. The nation becomes a substitute for God. The concept of civic religion is related to this idea and is closely related to the development of republican states in the ancient world.
At the close of the speech, Weber implores his audience to
balance what he calls an “ethic of ultimate ends” with an “ethic of
responsibility”, meaning that the goals which politicians strive for, like
creating a socialist society, need to be balanced by a concern for the
immediate actions one takes in order to pursue ultimate ends. In other words,
in a variation of the “ends justify the means” rationale, Weber says, the means
do count and cannot justify any goal no matter how good it sounds, bad means
are destructive of good ends. This is a strong statement to make when people
are questioning the most basic moral values they had been brought up on. At the
same time he realizes that in politics, good politics often comes from using
bad means as he says recounting a conversation he has with a friend who thought
he could get around the “ends justify the means” argument:
My colleague, Mr. F. W. Förster, whom personally I highly esteem for his undoubted sincerity, but whom I reject unreservedly as a politician, believes it is possible to get around this difficulty by the simple thesis: ‘from good comes only good; but from evil only evil follows.’ In that case this whole complex of questions would not exist. But it is rather astonishing that such a thesis could come to light two thousand five hundred years after the Upanishads. Not only the whole course of world history, but every frank examination of everyday experience points to the very opposite. The development of religions all over the world is determined by the fact that the opposite is true. The age-old problem of theodicy consists of the very question of how it is that a power which is said to be at once omnipotent and kind could have created such an irrational world of undeserved suffering, unpunished injustice, and hopeless stupidity. Either this power is not omnipotent or not kind, or, entirely different principles of compensation and reward govern our life—principles we may interpret metaphysically, or even principles that forever escape our comprehension (p. 122)
The constant exercise of power requires some form of
continuous organization which requires an administrative staff to carry out the
needs and demands of the organization in order to maintain itself and to carry
out its objectives. Officials who work within the state can be separated by
those who play 1) an internal function maintaining the organization itself:
paying its bills, securing supplies and resources, etc; and 2) external those
who carry out the objectives of the organization and realize the goals for
which the organization is created. Often times these require separate skills
and that is why these types of officials can be separated. This division is
more or less common throughout every political system at all times.
Weber then goes on to explain the historical development of
modern states from feudal monarchies to large nation-states. Weber explains
this development through a process of rationalization of political domination. Rationalization, again, is the
process of refining work tasks into repetitive, efficient procedures that
maximize the use of resources. Rationalization in the economic sphere shows the development of small family
owned business firms employing often crude methods of production into large
centralized corporations that are able to employ vast amounts of capital into constructing
advanced technological means of production and distribution. Workers are
inserted into the process of production by performing a singular task that is
repeated endlessly and systematically produces a product through the combining
of these tasks, otherwise known as the assembly line. Other more skilled
workers, are drilled incessantly from an early age to acquire the necessary
technical and administrative skill in order to run the machines and run the
corporation. While other workers are employed that specialize in distribution.
Rationalization in the political sphere shows a similar
development. Feudal governments divided power between kings who exercised
direct control over their own land and indirect control over the rest of the
kingdom through feudal nobles. Nobles up until the 16th century
often owned the “means of administration” meaning that they themselves owned
and managed the courts, the jails, bridges and toll roads, parks and hunting
grounds, and other “public” property and usually exercised final authority over
local matters. In exchange for this autonomy the nobles would grant the king
military service of himself and of the people he rules over. After the 16th
century there is a noticeable tendency towards centralization of political
power in the capital owing to developments in technology: military,
communication, and transportation technology (all undergoing their own process of rationalization) that allow for greater
concentration of power.
The major difference between traditional and modern states, Weber says, is one authority that controls the use of power and the officials who operate the machinery of government do not themselves own the machinery. Weber compares this to the way in which workers are separated from owning the production equipment they use to work. The growth in political power of the central government is made possible by the development of expert officials who attend to the needs of government. There had always been part time politicians, or people who influenced politics for their own affairs. But after the 16th century there is an increasing development in professional politicians developing first in the areas of war, finance, and law, these being the areas most important for the rulers power and too important to be turned over to part time politicians.
The major difference between traditional and modern states, Weber says, is one authority that controls the use of power and the officials who operate the machinery of government do not themselves own the machinery. Weber compares this to the way in which workers are separated from owning the production equipment they use to work. The growth in political power of the central government is made possible by the development of expert officials who attend to the needs of government. There had always been part time politicians, or people who influenced politics for their own affairs. But after the 16th century there is an increasing development in professional politicians developing first in the areas of war, finance, and law, these being the areas most important for the rulers power and too important to be turned over to part time politicians.
The most important attribute for a professional politician
is time, the time necessary to devote oneself to learning the intricacies of
the political art. Also if the politician is not to derive a living entirely
‘off’ of politics and live ‘for’ politics, he must also be “economically
dispensable” meaning he does not depend upon politics at all for an income. In
modern times former President Franklin Roosevelt, also former Governor of New
York came from one of the wealthiest and oldest families in New York going back
to the original Dutch settlers. Even more recently, former governor Eliot
Spitzer’s father was Bernard Spitzer, a New York real estate tycoon who owned
many large apartment and office buildings in New York City. Gov. Spitzer first as attorney general
and later as governor built his reputation as the “Sheriff of Wall St” despite
his wealthy background. Weber says, “under normal conditions, the politician
must be economically independent of the income politics can bring him. However according to this meaning Mitt Romney would also be Weber's ideal politician. This
means quite simply, that the politician must be wealthy or must have a personal
position in life which yields a sufficient income” (p. 85). He also says:
The leadership of a state or of a party by men who (in the economic sense of the word) live exclusively for politics and not off politics means necessarily a ‘plutocratic’ [rule of the wealthy, after the Roman god of wealth and the underworld, Pluto—Prof.] recruitment of the leading political strata. To be sure, this does not mean that such plutocratic leadership signifies at the same time that the politically dominant strata will not also seek to live ‘off’ politics, and hence that the dominant stratum will not usually exploit their political domination in their own economic interest (pp. 85-6)
In modern day states, politics is carried out through
political parties, which he defines as “management through interest groups” (p.
94) and tends to be recruited from the legal profession. Weber separates
professional politicians into two categories: 1) political leadership who lead and
represent the organization or department to the public and to the rest of the
government and who are distinct because they are transient, they are the ones
who come and go when different parties or rulers are in power; 2)
administration officials, the permanent officials who stay on despite who is in
power and make up the middle managers of government agencies.
The growth of professional officials who perform specialized
work processes organized into a ruling hierarchy under one central authority is
bureaucracy. It is a form of
organization that occurs at a certain level of complexity of an organization,
when technical full time skill is necessary to maintain the organization. The
Germans had a developed tradition of bureaucratic organization that is missing
in America. Almost all political offices in America changed according to
elections up until the 1880s (the notable exception is the judicial branch of
government). In the Weimar Constitution the special class of German civil
servants that have been developing since the 1700s (Beamte) have their own rights and responsibilities outlined
in the Constitution.
Rationalization of politics does not mean that freedom,
justice, or equality is increased. It refers only to the ability for political
decisions to be carried out with increased effectiveness.
Weber describes some of the major social groups that have
been recruited into the ranks of officialdom or “politically exploitable
strata” in Weber’s words. He gives special emphasis to the “university trained jurist”.
A jurist is one who is trained in manipulating the rules and procedures of the
legal system, jurisprudence. Modern
jurisprudence developed out of Roman law, used to administer the empire and was
very procedural, and Christian natural law theories which were later
secularized into modern legal systems. Lawyers, the most common jurist, play a
special role in modern politics because they possess the required technical
skill to manipulate the machinery of government. They are also more dispensable
in terms of time, unlike the entrepreneur, who in most cases Weber says makes a
bad politician precisely because so much time is needed to watch over the
business enterprise. Weber also tends to separate out the more charismatic
trial lawyers who are more suited for playing the political roles of
leadership, while the more scholarly jurist who plays a more behind the scenes
role, writing and interpreting complicated legal texts, makes a perfect
administration official. He again emphasizes the different skills both of these
groups possess and how they tend to be exclusive. He says the division head
often knows more than the minister, but complains about administration
officials being unfit for leadership (Beamtenherrschaft).
Weber contends that civil servants and political leaders
have two different conceptions of honor which means they have different
concepts of success and prestige in carrying out their duties:
The honor of the civil servant is vested in his ability to execute conscientiously the order of the superior authorities, exactly as if the order agreed with his own conviction. This holds even if the order appears wrong to him and if, despite the civil servant’s remonstrances, the authority insists on the order. Without this moral discipline and self-denial, in the highest sense, the whole apparatus would fall to pieces. The honor of the political leader, of the leading statesman, however, lies precisely in an exclusive personal responsibility for what he does, a responsibility he cannot and must not reject or transfer. It is in the nature of officials of high moral standing to be poor politicians, and above all, in the political sense of the word, to be irresponsible politicians (p. 95).
Within the ranks of political leadership, Weber sees a
division between the technical leader and the emotional leader. The emotional
leader is the king or the president, the one who commands the emotional loyalty
of the following. The technical leader is the one deals with the day to day affairs
of government, and is the one who has to deal with different government
agencies and parties, the one who gets his or her “hands dirty”. The prestige
of the emotional leader is preserved because they are insulated from having to
boss people around in order to get results, the technical leader takes on this
task. The Grand Vizier played this role for the sultan, as did the German
chancellor in the empire and the republic, or the prime minister in England and
the queen (emotional leader). Today’s modern American president has two
officials that play this role, the chief of staff, and the vice-president.
Furthermore he says that the leader must possess distinct
skills that cannot be taught, the ability to combine passion with cold
discipline:
This is the decisive psychological quality of the politician: his ability to let realities work upon him with inner concentration and calmness. Hence his distance to things and men. ‘Lack of distance’ per se is one of the deadly sins of every politician. It is one of those qualities the breeding of which will condemn the progeny of our intellectuals to political incapacity. For the problem is simply how can warm passion and a cool sense of proportion be forged together in one and the same soul? Politics is made with the head, not with other parts of the body or soul. And yet devotion to politics, if it is not to be frivolous intellectual play but rather genuinely human conduct, can be born and nourished from passion alone. (p. 115)
Marxist theory had stressed that all social conflicts originated in the
struggle between competing economic classes (more broadly defined as rich v.
poor). Capitalism was a specific form or mode of production that not only
enriched the few at the expense of the many but unleashed vast productive
forces that had been dormant for centuries leading to a tremendous material
improvement in the quality of life (for some) but also created unprecedented
means of control over the workers who were a dependent but necessary part of
the whole social process of production. Government, was itself the tool of the
ruling economic classes which used the power of the state to protect its
property through the courts and the legal system and through the use of
soldiers to put down strikes and labor disputes. Weber does not object to these
assertions as false but adds that the political realm has its own unique
existence that is not dependent on the economic, but that in fact the relation
between the politics and economics is more of a mutual feedback process, the political exerts influence
over the economic and vice versa. In later disputes over the origins of the
Nazi regime the dispute over the primacy of the economic over the political
will be stressed again.
Although Weber shows ambivalence over the direction of the
modern world: industrialization; monopoly capitalism; political
bureaucratization and recognizes the negative aspects of these developments, he still
defends bureaucratic organization (and by extension capitalism) as a superior
form of political organization to that which only tries to live ‘off’ politics
through patronage, political job placement:
The development of modern officialdom into a highly qualified, professional labor force, specialized in expertness through long years of preparatory training, stands opposed to all these arrangements. Modern bureaucracy in the interest of integrity has developed a high sense of status honor; without this sense the danger of an awful corruption and a vulgar Philistinism threatens fatally. And without such integrity, even the purely technical functions of the state apparatus would be endangered (p.88).
The opposite tendency towards patronage and job-seeking
grows more as politics becomes more bureaucratized, “this tendency becomes
stronger for all parties when the number of offices increase as a result of
general bureaucratization and when the demand for offices increases because
they represent specifically secure livelihoods. For their followings, the
parties become more and more a means to the end of being provided for in this
manner” (p. 87) In other words political parties which organize groups for
political competition (interelectoral compromises, unified programs endorsed by
broad segments of the population, unified agitation for these programs p. 101)
become essentially job placement machines. These activities are funded and
interrelated to the party’s other primary function—fundraising.
Although he praises the achievements and efficiency of
bureaucratic rationality, ultimately all politics takes one into the realm of
violence:
Whoever wants to engage in politics at all, and especially in politics as a vocation, has to realize these ethical paradoxes. He must know that he is responsible for what he may become of himself under the impact of these paradoxes. I repeat, he lets himself in for the diabolic forces lurking in all violence. The great virtuosi of acosmic love of humanity and goodness whether stemming from Nazareth or Assisi or from Indian royal castles, have not operated with the political means of violence. Their kingdom was ‘not of this world’ and yet they worked and still work in this world. The figures of Platon Karatajev and the saints of Dostoievski still remain their most adequate reconstructions. He who seeks the salvation of the soul of his own and of others, should not seek it along the avenue of politics, for the quite different tasks of politics can only be solved by violence [italics added]. The genius or demon of politics lives in an inner tension with the god of love, as well as with the Christian God as expressed by the church. This tension can at any time lead to an irreconcilable conflict. (pp. 125-26)
He closes with a rather nihilistic (and prophetic) message:
It would be nice if matters turned out in such a way that Shakespeare’s Sonnet 102 should hold true:
Our love was new, and then but in the spring,When I was wont to greet it with my lays;As Philomel in summer’s front doth sing,And stops her pipe in growth of riper days.
But such is not the case. Not summer’s bloom lies ahead of us, but rather a polar night of icy darkness and hardness, no matter which group may triumph externally now. Where there is nothing, not only the Kaiser but also the proletarian has lost his rights. When this night shall have slowly receded, who of those for whom spring apparently has bloomed so luxuriously will be alive? And what will have become of all of you by then? Will you be bitter or banausic? Will you simply and dully accept world and occupation? Or will the third and by no means the least frequent possibility be your lot: mystic flight from reality for those who are gifted for it, or—as is both frequent and unpleasant—for those who belabor themselves to follow this fashion? In every one of such cases, I shall draw the conclusion that they have not measured up to their own doings. They have not measured up to the world as it really is in its everyday routine. Objectively and actually, they have not experienced the vocation for politics in its deepest meaning, which they thought they had. They would have done better in simply cultivating plain brotherliness in personal relations. And for the rest—they should have gone soberly about their daily work (p. 128)
Next class we will look at the rise of Nazism and its consequences for Germany and the world.
Assignment Due 4/18 Choose a passage from Weber, write out the passage. Then explain the meaning of it, and then explain why you chose this passage.
References:
Assignment Due 4/18 Choose a passage from Weber, write out the passage. Then explain the meaning of it, and then explain why you chose this passage.
References:
- Barrington Moore Jr., Social Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy: Lord and Peasant in the Making of the Modern World, Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1966
- Dietrich Rueschemeyer, Evelyne Huber Stephens, and John Stephens, Capitalist Development and Democracy, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1992
- Gregory Luebbert, Liberalism, Fascism, or Social Democracy: Social Classes and the Political Origins of Regimes in Interwar Europe, New York: Oxford University Press, 1991
- Daron Acemoglu and James Robinson, Economic Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006
- Reinhard Bendix, Nation-Building and Citizenship, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, [1964] 1977
- Max Weber, From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. Hans Gerth and C. Wright Mills, New York: Oxford University Press, 1944
- Max Weber, Economy and Society, trans. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, [1922] 1978
- G.W.F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, trans. H.B. Nisbet, New York: Cambridge University Press [1820] 1991
- Charles Tilly, "War Making and State Making as Organized Crime," in Peter Evans, Dietrich Rueschemeyer and Theda Skocpol, Bringing the State Back In, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1985, pp. 169-91
- Charles Tilly (ed.), The Formation of National States in Western Europe, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975
- Perry Anderson, Lineages of the Absolutist State, New York: Verso, 1974
- Michael Mann, "The Autonomous Power of the State," Archives de Européenes de Sociologie, Vol. 25, No. 19, (1984), pp. 185-213
- Thomas Ertman, Birth of the Leviathan: Building States and Regimes in Medieval and Early Modern Europe, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997
- Alexander Gerschenkron, Economic Backwardness in Historical Perspective: A Book of Essays, Westport, CT: Frederick A. Praeger, 1962